Foundations of Modern Science: 

Faith, Philosophy, and the Search for Truth


Beneath the surface of scientific facts lies a world of philosophical questions. This essay explores the assumptions that make science possible, from the nature of truth to the limits of empirical observation.


Published October 2022 - Updated March 16, 2025

Science presents itself as the paragon of objective inquiry—a realm where facts reign supreme and subjective beliefs are left at the laboratory door. Yet beneath the equations and experiments lies a foundation of philosophical assumptions that make scientific practice possible in the first place. These assumptions aren't typically proven by science itself (indeed, they can't be without circular reasoning); rather, they constitute the necessary preconditions for scientific inquiry to function at all.

When a physicist discusses quantum entanglement or a biologist describes evolutionary mechanisms, they are invoking not only empirical findings but also centuries of philosophical deliberation about what constitutes knowledge, causation, and explanation. This hidden architecture of ideas deserves our attention, not to undermine scientific authority, but to deepen our appreciation of how science actually works.

Causality: Science's Leap of Faith

One of the most fundamental assumptions in science is causality: the idea that events have discernible causes and follow consistent laws. Without this assumption, experiments would be meaningless—we run experiments precisely to determine what causes what.

Yet as David Hume famously argued in the 18th century, our belief in causality relies on a logical leap. We infer future patterns from past observations (the sun rose yesterday, so we expect it will rise tomorrow), but such inference has no absolute logical guarantee. We assume nature's uniformity—that physical laws tomorrow will be like those today—but we cannot prove this using logic or even science itself. Any attempt to justify induction by saying "it worked in the past" simply begs the question, since that itself assumes patterns will continue.

Immanuel Kant responded to Hume by suggesting that the human mind necessarily imposes causal order on experience—that causality is a prerequisite for intelligible experience. Ludwig Wittgenstein later offered his own critique, famously writing, "Superstition is the belief in the causal nexus. " Wittgenstein wasn't suggesting we abandon causality in practice but was highlighting the mysterious leap from one event to another when examined rigorously.

This unsettling thought doesn't stop scientists from seeking causes. Every successful experiment reinforces our confidence that causality is reliable. But it's worth recognizing that one of science's bedrock assumptions—that the world has an orderly chain of causes—rests on a philosophical leap of faith.

From Verification to Falsification: Defining Scientific Meaning

How do we know if a scientific statement is meaningful or true? In the early 20th century, the Logical Positivists argued that statements only have meaning if they can be verified through empirical observation. This stance, known as verificationism, attempted to distinguish meaningful scientific claims from metaphysical speculation.

However, verificationism encountered problems. Universal laws (like "All swans are white") can never be conclusively verified—no matter how many white swans you observe, you can't be certain a black swan isn't hiding somewhere. (In fact, I once saw a black swan swimming in a lake! ) Moreover, the verificationist criterion itself couldn't be verified by its own standards.

Karl Popper proposed falsificationism as an alternative: a hypothesis is scientific not if it can be verified, but if it can be falsified. In other words, scientific theories should make predictions that could, in principle, prove them wrong. Einstein's general relativity was scientific because it made bold, testable predictions. In contrast, Popper considered astrology pseudoscientific because its claims are too flexible to be definitively falsified.

This Popperian perspective remains influential. The notion that "no number of experiments can ever prove a theory right, but a single experiment can prove it wrong" instills a certain intellectual humility: our best theories are always provisional, and we must be willing to revise them when evidence demands it.

Paradigm Shifts: When Scientific Worlds Collide

If Popper portrayed scientific progress as incremental falsification and refinement, Thomas Kuhn complicated this picture by examining the history of science. In his influential book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), Kuhn argued that science advances not linearly but through periods of stable growth under a prevailing paradigm—an overarching framework of theories, methods, and assumptions  - punctuated by occasional revolutions where that framework collapses and a new one emerges.

During periods of "normal science," scientists largely accept foundational principles and focus on solving puzzles within the established paradigm. However, as anomalies accumulate—results that don't align with the paradigm's predictions—confidence can waver. Eventually, a crisis may precipitate a paradigm shift: a revolutionary reframing that redefines fundamental concepts, as when Einstein's relativity overturned Newtonian conceptions of space and time.

Kuhn's provocative claim was that different paradigms can be incommensurable—they may involve such different concepts and methods that scientists from different paradigms struggle to fully understand each other. After a revolution, scientists adopt new assumptions, and even what counts as an explanation or valid experiment can change.

This perspective reveals that scientific "truths" are, to some extent, historically contingent. Science might not be steadily approaching Ultimate Truth, but rather occasionally leaping onto entirely new tracks that redefine what truth looks like in a given domain. Kuhn didn't claim science is merely subjective—it certainly progresses—but not in the simple, cumulative way that Popperian falsification suggests.

Unity or Disunity: The Organization of Scientific Knowledge

Is scientific knowledge fundamentally unified, or legitimately divided into distinct domains? Many Enlightenment thinkers and 20th-century philosophers hoped that all branches of knowledge could integrate into a coherent system. The logical positivists envisioned a grand reduction: chemistry and biology ultimately reducible to physics, psychology to biology, sociology to psychology—everything explained by a common scientific language.

In practice, however, strict unity has proven elusive. Members of the "Stanford School" (including Nancy Cartwright, John Dupré, and Ian Hacking) have argued that different sciences legitimately operate with different methods, concepts, and even different understandings of what constitutes a "cause" or "explanation." The way a sociologist explains a social revolution may be fundamentally different from how a physicist explains planetary motion, and these explanations may not neatly reduce to one another.

This debate touches a profound epistemological question: Is reality inherently unified such that one description covers all, or is it more like a patchwork requiring multiple conceptual maps? The unity assumption motivates pursuits like a "Theory of Everything" in physics, while the pluralist counter-argument suggests that nature has various levels of organization that don't smoothly reduce to one another.

Modern science operates pragmatically between these views. A biologist doesn't worry daily about reconciling her work with quantum mechanics, yet many scientists assume some kind of ultimate consistency across disciplines. The periodic table was explained by quantum physics; genetics was grounded in molecular DNA mechanisms. These successes of reduction give hope that fragmentation is temporary, but the organization of knowledge into disciplines remains partly historical accident and practical necessity.

The Nature of Scientific Explanation

What does it mean to explain something scientifically? This seemingly straightforward question reveals deeper complexities upon examination. Science assumes the world is intelligible—that we can make sense of phenomena through explanation—but the very concept of "explanation" isn't as simple as it first appears.

The classic Deductive-Nomological model proposed by Carl Hempel suggests that to explain something is to show it was expected under general laws. Why did the window break? Because a rock hit it, and given laws of physics regarding force and brittle materials, the breaking was predictable. But philosophers quickly realized this model has limitations. Explanation can be asymmetric—while you could technically "explain" a flagpole's height from its shadow length using geometry, we intuitively recognize that the flagpole causes the shadow, not vice versa.

In many sciences, especially biology and social sciences, explanations often take the form of narratives or mechanisms rather than strict laws. Wesley Salmon argued that explanations are frequently causal-mechanical: to explain an event is to trace the network of causes and effects that produced it. Philip Kitcher proposed that good explanations unify disparate phenomena under simpler frameworks - Newton explaining both falling apples and orbiting moons with the same gravitational theory.

There's also a pragmatic view that what counts as explanation depends on context and the questions being asked. A meteorologist explaining a tornado provides a different account than someone asking why the tornado struck their particular town—both questions seek explanation, but of fundamentally different kinds.

Modern science employs multiple approaches to explanation: laws, causes, models, simulations, and unifying theories. As John von Neumann observed, "The sciences do not try to explain, they hardly even try to interpret; they mainly make models." If our models reliably predict and allow for control of outcomes, science is generally satisfied, even if philosophical questions about ultimate reality remain open.

The Limits of Empiricism and the Need for Philosophy

Finally, we come to empiricism itself—the doctrine that knowledge derives primarily from sensory experience. Modern science depends fundamentally on observation, measurement, and experiment. We build elaborate instruments to extend our senses, all assuming that careful observation corresponds to aspects of reality.

Yet data alone doesn't speak—it requires interpretation through theoretical frameworks, and these interpretations are inevitably influenced by prior assumptions. This is the insight that observations are theory-laden - what we observe is shaped by what we expect or the concepts we employ. A neuroscientist and a shaman observing the same behavior might "see" entirely different phenomena because their conceptual frameworks diverge.

Another limitation is that many scientifically meaningful entities cannot be directly observed. Theoretical constructs like quarks, black holes, or the curvature of spacetime are inferred rather than seen. Even everyday concepts like "force" or "energy" are not directly visible but are operationalized through their effects. This challenges strict empiricism and leads to debates between scientific realism (these unobservable entities are real) and nominalism (they are useful fictions).

Moreover, empiricism itself cannot justify the principles of empiricism. Why trust our senses? Why assume an external world exists at all? - the question Descartes asked at the beginning of modernity. These questions might seem abstruse, but they underscore that science presupposes an orderly, knowable external reality—an assumption that enables scientific inquiry but is not itself proven by science.

There are also moral and existential limits to empiricism. Science can explain how to build nuclear weapons but not whether we should. It can model climate change but doesn't by itself tell us what values should guide our response. The empirical method excels at "how" questions but must often defer to philosophy and other domains for questions of meaning, purpose, and ethics.

Where We Stand Today: Science in a Philosophical World

Modern science presents itself as self-sufficient, requiring only objective observation and rational analysis. But as we've seen, it rests on a rich foundation of philosophical presuppositions about causality, verification, explanation, unification, and empiricism—assumptions that make scientific inquiry meaningful in the first place.

Today's science operates in a complex landscape of competing philosophical perspectives. Most practicing scientists embrace a pragmatic blend of realism about their theories while acknowledging their provisional nature. The spectacular achievements of contemporary science—from CRISPR gene editing to the detection of gravitational waves—testify to the practical power of this approach, even as philosophical questions about scientific knowledge remain open.

Interestingly, frontier areas of science often force reconsideration of foundational assumptions. Quantum mechanics continues to challenge intuitive notions of causality, realism, and locality. Cognitive science raises questions about the nature of mind and consciousness that blur traditional boundaries between objective and subjective knowledge. Climate science and pandemic response highlight the complex interplay between scientific facts and human values in addressing global challenges.

These developments suggest that the relationship between science and philosophy is not hierarchical but dialogical. Philosophy is not merely a synthesis of scientific results, nor is science simply applied philosophy. Rather, they engage in a continuing conversation, with philosophy clarifying the conceptual foundations of scientific inquiry and science providing new phenomena that demand philosophical reflection.

The "miracle" of science—its remarkable ability to produce reliable knowledge about the world—is built on conceptual foundations that themselves cause us to wonder and reflect. By engaging with the philosophies of science, we don't undermine confidence in scientific results; we enrich our understanding of how those results are possible and what they ultimately mean.

In the end, modern science requires a form of rational faith: faith in an ordered universe, faith in our capacities to comprehend that order, and faith that our provisional theories, however imperfect, guide us toward deeper understanding. These fundamental assumptions are the quiet companions of every scientific breakthrough—unseen, often unspoken, but absolutely essential to science's continuing journey.