Aristotle's View of Politics

Aristotle's political philosophy is consistent with his metaphysics. His metaphysics is based on a philosophy of nature that can be extended to social bodies. Aristotle's view of nature starts with an interpretation of causality, because he wants to create a framework that would help him to explain change and motion. Aristotle distinguishes four ways in which we respond to the why? question: We can point to the material cause (what something is made of), the formal cause (its definition, the idea that is embodied in it), the efficient cause (how it was created) and the final cause (the reason for which it was created.)  This view of causality implies an ethics built into nature: things are good when they are created or built well and serve their natural purposes. Aristotle's philosophy of nature can easily be applied to human societies as well, and it results in a political theory that has withstood the test of time.  

The notion of final cause dominates Aristotle's "Politics" from the opening lines: "Since we see that every city-state is a sort of community and that every community is established for the sake of some good (for everyone does everything for the sake of what they believe to be good), it is clear that every community aims at some good, and the community which has the most authority of all and includes all the others aims highest, that is, at the good with the most authority. This is what is called the city-state or political community. [Politics Book I.1.1252a1–7]

He also states in the opening chapters that the city-state comes into being for "the sake of life but exists for the sake of the good life." The theme that the good life or happiness is the proper end of the city-state recurs throughout this foundational text of Western Political Philosophy. 

The state is a community (koinônia), a collection of elements that have some functions and interests in common.  If we apply Aristotle's theory of causation to the existence of political units like States, it is evident that the State is composed as a "hylemorphism," a matter-form compound, and the following scheme emerges: 



Aristotle's political theory follows from his metaphysics that explains nature through its internal principle of motion and rest (Aristotle, Physics, Book III.1.192b8–15). Human societies emerge as natural entities that unleash human potential.  He makes four claims  about nature and the city-state: 


Aristotle uses the term "nature" in a vague and somewhat undefined sense. States are not entirely natural, otherwise they would be beehives or ant colonies. Applied to humans, who are by nature intelligent, the State can become a product of culture: the law givers, or the sovereign, turn the natural potential in humans into the artificially created system of the State that develops through history. 

The Aristotelian view of politics is based on the following assumptions: